Sunday, May 19, 2019

Presocratic Philosophy Essay

opening As early Greek shade grew more complex (c. 500 b. c. e. ), mythology and religion began to develop into philosophy (and later into science). As part of this using, a new kind of thinker emerged inhabitn as a sophos, from the Greek cry for wise. These wise men, and they were approximately exclusively men, asked increasingly sophisticated questions to the highest degree on the unit sorts of things, especi ally natural litigatees and the origins and essence of intent.Although mythology and religion go along to play cardinal roles in the lives of people for centuries to come, these first philosophers were noned for their attempts to use reason and observation to show out how the world works. Instead of upkeep a modal(prenominal) spiritedness, the sophos devoted himself to asking questions that so-cal lead normal people thought had already been answered (by religion and mythology) or were unanswerable (and thus a waste of time).In respect to public perceptions, it didnt help that the sophos lived and spoke in counsels that were interpreted as screening disregard and possibly disrespect for conventional values, and that set him or (infrequently) her apart from regular folks living normal lives. It is hardly surprising, then, that one of the earliest popular images of philosophers is the stereotype of an odd, absent-minded, starry-eyed dreamer and asker of loco questions. The genuinely first Western thinkers identified as philosophers were initially concerned with questions about the character of nature (physis) and of the world order (kosmos).presocratic Rational Discourse The earliest Western philosophers are referred to as the pre-Socratics because they appeared forward to Socrates, the first major figure in the Western philosophical tradition. Some of the Presocratic philosophers are set forth as proto-scientists because they initiated the transformation of mythology into sharp inquiry about nature and the cosmos. A very general word picture of the development of Presocratic philosophy is helpful for placing subsequent philosophical issues and disagreements in context.Ofmost interest for our purposes is the Presocratic philosophers struggle to offer rational, objective arguments and explanations for their pull ins. These concerns played a major role in the origins and historical development of Western philosophy. The first philosophers intense interest in explanations shaped the development of reason by triggering questions of sensible consistency and standards of knowledge that went beyond the sorts of evidence that a craftsman could offer to back up his claims to expertise.The Presocratic Philosophers Thales Thales (c. 624545 b. c. e.), traditionally said to be the first Western philosopher, seems to consent believed that water is in some way central to our understanding of things. This concept was probably based upon a belief that the state floated on water, and that all things originate with water. Current opinion holds that Thales believed that whatever is real is in some significant sense alive. concord to Aristotle, Thales thought that all things are full of gods, and as evidence of such powers even in simply inanimate nature he points to the remarkable properties of what was referred to as the Magnesian stone.Although Aristotles statement is too discount to serve as a sure foundation for judgment, it seems more likely that Thales was arguing for the broader presence of life forces in the world than most people imagined, rather than that the real in its totality is alive. Anaximander Thales younger modern from Miletus, Anaximander, born toward the end of the seventh century B. C. E. , found the explanatory article of belief of things in what he called the apeiron, a word that might be translated as the indefinite, the boundless(prenominal), or both.This opens up the possibility that the apeiron is both immeasurably colossal in its temporal and physiologic extent an d also qualitatively indefinite in that it is without measurable internal boundaries. The apeiron is further described, according to Aristotle, as being without beginning, surrounding all things, steering all things, divine, immortal, and indestructible. Some have inferred that Anaximanders barely concealed purpose was Western philosophys first attempt at demythologization.Equally striking is Anaximanders description of the earth as a closed, concentric dust, the outer spheres of which, by their everlasting motion, account for the stability of our earth, a drum-shaped body held everlastingly in a state of rest at the center. Whatever the inadequacy in certain details (the stars are posed nearer to the earth than the moon), with Anaximander the science of cosmo logical speculation took a giant step forward. As far as life on earth is concerned, Anaximander offered an opposite striking hypothesis.The first living things, according to him, were born in moisture, enwrap in tho rny barks (like sea urchins), and as their age increased, they came forth onto the drier part (as phrased by Aetius first to minute of arc century C. E. ). Pythagoras Although we know that Pythagoras was a historical figure, it is difficult to determine exactly what Pythagoras himself taught. He wrote nothing, and the ideas of other members of the club were attributed to him as a sign of respect and as a way of lending weight to the ideas.Plato and Aristotle rarely assign ideas to Pythagoras himself, although Pythagorean ideas seem to have influenced Platos philosophy. Pythagoreans asserted that number is the first principle of all things. They were the first systematic developers of mathematics in the West and discovered that natural events could be described in mathematical terms, especially as ratios. To the Pythagoreans, the principle of number accounted for everything. Number was a real thing. Somehow, numbers existed in space, not just as mental constructs.According to Pyth agorean doctrine, the entire universe is an ordered whole consisting of harmonies of contrasting elements. The Greek for ordered whole is cosmos. The Pythagoreans were the first philosophers to use the term cosmos to refer to the universe in this way. The celestial music of the spheres is the hauntingly beautiful phrase the Pythagoreans coined to describe the sound of the heavens as they rise according to cosmic number and harmony.Xenophanes A fourth Ionian philosopher, Xenophanes of Colophon, born around 580 B. C. E. ,is the first we know of to overtly attack the anthropomorphism of popular religious belief, in a series of brilliant reductio ad absurdum ad absurdum arguments. His cause view has been understood, ever since Aristotle, as pantheistic. Xenophanes was also the first philosopher we know of to ask what degree of knowledge is attainable. In B34 we read the clear and certain truth no man has seen, nor will in that respect be anyone who knows about the gods and what I s ay about all things. Several ancient critics took this to be an reading of Xenophanes total scepticism.On this basis of moderate empiricism and scepticism, Xenophanes offered a number of opinions of varying plausibility about the natural world, one of whicha strong, evolutionary interpretation of the discovery on various islands of fossils of marine animalsis rich to constitute a major claim to fame in natural philosophy and ranks with his other significant locomote in epistemology (the theory of knowledge dealing with what we know, how we know it, and how reliable our knowledge is), logic (the study of rational inquiry and argumentation), and natural theology (the attempt to understand God from natural knowledge).Heraclitus One of the most important and enigmatic of the Presocratics, Heraclitus (fl . 500 b. c. e. , d. 510480 b. c. e. ), said that ignorance is bound to result when we try to understand the cosmos when we do not even comprehend the basic structure of the human psyc he (soul) and its relationship to the Logos. The complex Greek word logos is intriguing.It could and at times did mean all of the following intelligence, speech, discourse, thought, reason, word, meaning, study of, the record of, the science of, the primordial principles of, the basic principles and procedures of a particular discipline, those features of a thing that make it intelligible to us, and the rationale for a thing. The Heraclitean majuscule L Logos is like God, only without the anthropomorphizing (humanizing) of the earlier philosophers and poets who attributed human qualities to the gods.According to Heraclituss impersonal view of God, the Logos is a work on, not an entity. As such, the Logos is unconcerned with individuals and human affairs, in much the equal way that gravity affects us but is unconcerned with us. More radically yet, Heraclitus asserted that even though things appear to remain the same, Change alone is unever-changing. Traditionally, it has been h eld that Heraclitus went so far as to claim that everything is always changing all the time. But whether he really meant that everything is always changing, or that individual things are held together by energy ( counterchange), remains unclear.Anaximenes Anaximanders younger contemporary, Anaximenes, who lived during the sixth century B. C. E. appears to revert to a prior and less sophisticated vision in claiming that the earth, far from being a drum-shaped body held in equipoise at the center, is flat and rides on, supported by air. The same might be said of his contention that the basic, divine principle of things was not some indefinite entity but something very much part of our experience namely, air.Anaximenes view would also no doubt have seemed to be corroborated by the fact that the universe, usually understood as a living thing and hence needing a soul to vivify it, possessed in air that very breath that for most Greeks constituted the essence of such a soul. Parmenides P armenides of Elea (fift h century b. c. e. ) radically change the early philosophers interest in cosmology, the study of the universe as a rationally ordered system (cosmos), into ontology, the study of being. By common agreement he was the giant among the pre-Socratics.According to Parmenides, none of his predecessors adequately accounted for the process by which the one basic stuff of the cosmos changes into the many individual things we experience every day. In his search for a solution to the problem of the one and the many, Parmenides turned to a reasoned analysis of the process of change itself. According to Parmenides, all sensations occur in the realm of appearance. This means that reality cannot be apprehend by the senses. Change and variety (the many) are only appearances they are not real. If this is true, then our most commonly held beliefs about reality are mere opinions.The senses cannot recognize what is, much less can they discover come upit, ever. In other words, whatever we see, touch, taste, hear, or smell is not real, does not exist. Perhaps most unsettling of all, Parmenides figure out the problem of the appearance of change by concludingin direct opposition to Heraclituss instancy that everything is always changingthat the very concept of change is self-contradictory. What we think of as change is merely an illusion. The logic runs as follows Change equals transformation into something else.When a thing becomes something else, it becomes what it is not. But since it is impossible for nothing (what is not) to exist, there is no nothing into which the old thing can disappear. (There is no no place for the thing to go into. ) Therefore, change cannot occur. Empedocles posited, against Parmenides, change and plurality as features of reality, but affirmed the eternality of anything that is real the sphere-like nature of the real when looked at as a totality and the fact that the real is a plenum, containing no nothingness or emptiness.Anax agoras withal posited change, plurality, and divisibility as features of reality, yet also affirmed the eternality of the real (understood by him as an eternally existent mixed bag of the seeds of the things currently constituting the world, rather than the eternal combinings and recombinings, according to certain ratios of admixture, of four eternally existent roots or elemental masses). Leucippus Leucippus of Miletus (c. fi ft h century b. c. e. ) and Democritus of Abdera (c. 460370 b.c. e. ) argued that reality consists entirely of empty space and ultimately dewy-eyed entities that combine to form objects.T is materialistic view is know as atomism. Leucippus is credited with being the power of atomism and Democritus with developing it. Rather than reject Parmenides assertion that change is an illusion, Leucippus argued that reality consists of many discrete ones, or beings. Zeno Zeno, who was born early in the fifth century B. C. E. , was a friend and pupil of Parmenides.In h is noted paradoxes he attempted to show by a series of reductio ad absurdum arguments, of which the best known is perhaps that of Achilles and the tortoise, the self-contradictory consequences of maintaining that there is a real plurality of things or that motion or place are real. The prima facie brilliance of many of the arguments continues to impress people, though it soon becomes clear that the paradoxes turn by and large on the failure or unwillingness of Zeno, like so many Pythagoreans of the day, to distinguish between the concepts of physical and geometrical space.Zenos way of constructing the problem makes it seem that his primary object is to defame pluralists by struggle the logical possibility of explaining how there can be motion in the world. Gorgias Gorgias has achieved fame for the stress he rigid upon the art of persuasion ( grandiosity), although whether he wrote the baffling On What Is Not as a knockout piece of persuasive reasoning or as some sort of spoof of the Eleatic philosophy of Parmenides and others remains disputed.Its basic, and remarkable, claim is prima facie, that nothing in fact is (exists /is the case esti or is knowable or conceivable. every exiguous plausibility that the arguments supporting this claim possess turns on our overlooking Gorgiass failure, witting or unwitting, to distinguish carefully between knowing and thinking, along with his various uses of the verb to be. If the failure was witting, the document can be seen as a skillful device for the spotting of fallacies as part of training in rhetoric and basic reasoning.If it was unwitting, Gorgias still emerges as what he was claimed to bea deft rhetorical wordsmith on any topic proposed to him. Protagoras Perhaps the greatest of the Sophists was Protagoras of Abdera (481 411 b. c. e. ). Protagoras was an archetypal Sophist an active traveler and first-rate observer of other cultures who noted that although there are a variety of customs and beliefs, each cultur e believes unquestioningly that its own ways are rightand roundly condemns (or at least criticizes) views that differ from its own.Based on his observations and travels, Protagoras reason out that morals are nothing more than the social traditions, or mores, of a society or group. The details of Protagorass beliefs remain disputed. When he said, for example, that anthropos humanity is a/the footmark for all things, of things that are, that they are, and of things that are not, that they are not, it is unclear whether he is talking about one person or the sum total of persons about a measure or the measure (there is no definite article in Greek) or about existence or states of affairs or both.The Platonic reading in the Theaetetus, which takes anthropos as generic and measure as exclusive, led to the assertion that the logical consequence was total (and absurd) relativism. ______________________________ References The Columbia History of Western Philosophy. Richard H. Popkin. Colum bia University Press. 1999. Archetypes of Wisdom An Introduction to Philosophy. 7th ed. Douglas J. Soccio. Wadsworth, Cengage Learning. 2010.

No comments:

Post a Comment

Note: Only a member of this blog may post a comment.